レヴィ・ブライアント
科学的自然主義者と観念論者の近代的反省
アッシャー・ケイ(Asher Kay)はOOOをある種の随伴現象説(epiphenomena)の論証として、「実在論・観念論論争の一手」(move in the battle between realism and idealism)と位置づけるが、ブライアントはフラットな存在論の契機として下記のように捉える。 OOO places all objects on equal ontological footing. ~ placing the two orders that characterize the discourse of modernity on a single ontological plane.
ここでいう「近代の言説を特徴づける二つの秩序(two orders that characterize the discourse of modernity)」とは、「科学的自然主義者(scientific naturalist)」の「自然(nature)」と、「観念論者(idealist)」の「文化(culture)」である。上記のように「単一の存在論的平面に(single ontological plane)」あらゆる対象を対等に位置づけようとする姿勢は、科学的自然主義者と観念論者の近代的反省と大きく異なる。なぜならラトゥールがいうように、科学的自然主義者も観念論者も、自然と文化の混同を「前近代(pre-modernity)」的「大罪(cardinal sin)」であるとして、二つの領域の「純化(purification)」をもって厳格な区分を示そうとするからだ。 That is, as analyzed by Latour, the key move of modernity is a purification of the two domains of nature and culture, such that the two are to be rigorously separated and held apart at pains of social catastrophe, disaster, superstition, and horror. The great sin of pre-modernity, claims both the scientific naturalist and the idealist is to confuse the two domains of nature and culture, object and subject.
例えば、科学的自然主義者は下記のように、世界の漸進的自然化(progressive naturalization of the world)によって、あらゆる観念論的対象を「随伴現象的文化(cultural epiphenomena)」のような二次的なものに位置づけ、文化と厳格に区分する。
Thus, the scientific naturalist believes that social progress will result from the progressive naturalization of the world. “No longer”, she says, “will we confuse the appearance of a comet with cultural epiphenomena like superstition that see it as a bad omen or sign!
Likewise, the idealist sees the cardinal sin of pre-modernity as the confusion of properly cultural phenomena with “natural” phenomena. “No longer”, she says, “will we see laws and society as natural orders as in the case of the Great Chain of Being, but rather we must carefully keep nature and culture separate such that we see that it is we that produce nature, laws, and society.” As Deleuze puts it in his gorgeous little book on Kant, “the first thing we discover with Kant’s moral philosophy is that it is we who are calling the shots.” The moral law is no longer a natural artifact, but is rather something that the subject gives to itself in and through its autonomy.
フラットな存在論としてのOOO
ここで冒頭のブライアンとのテーゼに戻りたい
The key point not to be missed with OOO is that the realism of object-oriented ontology is not making a decision within the framework of this schema or partition between nature and culture. OOO is not preoccupied with the question of whether being falls on the side of nature or of culture. Rather, in drawing a transversal line across nature and culture, the issue is no longer whether being falls into the circle of nature and culture, but rather in establishing a flat ontology united around a third line in which both domains (and the OOO theorist need not even speak of incommensurable domains any longer) now equally are. This is an entirely different sorting of the world and of the question of ontology.
続けてブライアントは自らの理論における「存在論的原則としての横断線(transversal line is the ontic principle)」 を差異を生成するものとして重要視する。そしてこの「横断線(transversal line)」によって、「brains, atoms, quarks, black holes, hurricanes」に留まらず―科学的自然主義者と異なり―「fictional entities, works of art, signs, Sweden, the United States Constitution, norms, narratives, tables, subjects」をもオヴジェクトとして扱う。これは何故なのか。
If the object-oriented ontologist is committed to a thesis as strange as the idea that a phoneme is an object or that Norway is an object, then this is because the criteria for being an object is not whether or not an entity is physical, but whether or not it makes differences.
One might object that this is a tremendous abuse of the word object and what we mean when we refer to existence. “Harry Potter does not exist!” To be sure, there is no physical referent of the character of Harry Potter. However, the fictional character of Harry Potter certainly exists and makes all sorts of differences to all sorts of other objects. It will again be objected that this is an abuse of the term “existence”. At this point, it becomes necessary to press the defender of the thesis that existence is equivalent to being-physical. “What is this quality you refer to as existence? What is it for something to exist?” “Well Sir, to exist is to be physical!” “And”, the onticologist asks in good Platonic fashion seeking to get at the hidden presuppositions already implicit in the thesis, “what does it mean to be physical?” All sorts of answers will be given to this question, but ultimately at the end of the day, at the completion of the dialogue, it will be found that what the scientific naturalist was claiming all along is that to exist is to make differences. That which exists is that which is capable of producing differences. But if this is the case, then it follows that we should practice an egalitarianism of difference, thereby arriving at a flat ontology. If to exist is to be capable of making differences, then whatever makes a difference is. This egalitarianism or ontological difference is not the thesis that all beings equally make differences, that they are all equally important (a normative judgment), that all differences are desirable or valuable (another normative judgment), but simply that regardless of the degree to which something makes a difference, if a difference is made then that thing is. The smallest fluctuation in temperature is still a temperature and still a difference in temperature. Likewise, the smallest difference is still a difference and therefore something that is. The microscopic mite or demodex that dwells in my eyelash makes very little difference to that lash or my body, but nonetheless makes differences and therefore is.
個人主義と全体主義について
In this post I get the sense that Tim is trying the navigate the Charybdis and Scylla of individualism and holism. そこでまず右翼のイデオロギーとしての個人主義を紹介する。
This variant of rightwing ideology received it’s most precisely and memorable formulation from Margaret Thatcher. As Thatcher famously said, “society does not exist.” She then added that there are only individuals and families. When Thatcher said that society does not exist, she meant that people are not products of social forces and conditions, but are rather products of themselves through their own sovereign decisions, choices, skills, and so on.
そこでその最たる例としてサッチャー(鉄の女)の政治思想を紹介する。有名な「社会は存在しない」というテーゼを紹介するとともにブルジョワ的系譜に立脚したヴィジョンを提供する。そこから二つの帰結を導く (1) If people are products of their own sovereign choices and make themselves, then they are responsible for where they are in society, and (2) other individuals and government institutions have no responsibilities to individuals in dire circumstances such as poverty. Rather, the function of government would be to protect the rights of individuals, protect the state, and punish crime; nothing more, nothing less. If we have no obligations to individuals in unfortunate circumstances, then this is because these individuals are where they are as a result of the poor choices they made. The poor person is not a product of poverty, but rather their own bad decisions. The criminal is not a product of social circumstances, but is the result of a crack in their being that leads him to crime. Such is the core thesis of liberalism and neoliberalism.
「other individuals and government institutions have no responsibilities to individuals in dire circumstances such as poverty. Rather, the function of government would be to protect the rights of individuals, protect the state, and punish crime; nothing more, nothing less. 」とあるようにサッチャリズムとは最小国家的である。 そこでまず次に左翼のイデオロギーとしての個人主義を紹介する。
From this vantage, we can see why holism becomes attractive. The holist rejoins that no, individuals are products of their relations or circumstances. Poverty produces poverty. Wealth produces wealth. Horrific living circumstances tend to produce horrific circumstances. Individuals do not choose these circumstances, but find themselves entangled in these circumstances. If this is the case, then individuals are not responsible for where they are because, to use a Heideggerian turn of phrase, they were thrown into a set of circumstances not of their own making that channel and form them in a particular way.
全体主義はハイデガー的に言い表しているように―恐らくこの言明は被投的投企のこと―被投性の次元にあらゆる問題を回収し、あくまで投企の次元に個人を位置づける。それゆえ「Poverty produces poverty. Wealth produces wealth. 」というマルクス的な表現になるのだ。 更に続けて「everything is inter-related」だからこそ「we are responsible to others」しよう!というのは個人主義の―「The poor person is not a product of poverty, but rather their own bad decisions」に代表とされるような―「If people are products of their own sovereign choices and make themselves, then they are responsible for where they are in society」な責任の対応関係にある。〔それゆえ原文で「responsible」を強調しているのでは?〕それゆえ社会は「countless contributions」によって構成されているとする。そして全体主義者はネガティブ・フィードバックがあらゆる社会的諸領域で発生していることを知っているとし下記のように述べる。 The holist recognizes that there are all sorts of negative feedback mechanisms at work in social relations. If the children of poor people themselves tend to grow up to be poor, then this is because there are all sorts of negative feedback relations that tend to draw that person back into the state of poverty even if they heroically push against it. These negative feedback relations include everything from malnutrition, to grueling work schedules required to survive (leaving little time for personal development), to the way employers react when they note that you don’t have the right sort of clothing, mannerisms, or speech (all the things that Bourdieu lists under habitus in texts like Homo Academicus and Distinction), to underfunded schools, to an absence of contacts in networks of wealth and power, etc. And likewise with wealth. Like rats in a maze with only one path, human bodies tend to be channeled into particular basins of attraction that reproduce the organization of the social order along certain hierarchical lines. These hierarchical lines involve economic class, symbolic capital or position, race, gender, religion, etc.
Third dimension―OOO politics
まずブライアントは下記にあるように「OOO politics」の次元が、一見すると右翼イデオロギーに近しいかのように感じる、とする。
In its focus on individual objects, OOO sounds as if it defends, at the level of ontology, the foundations of the rightwing ideology outlined above. In defending a conception of being premised on discrete and unrelated objects it sounds as if OOO is providing ontological ammunition for a rightwing account of the world.
そこでブライアントは「intellectual universe of rightwing thought: vacuum space」として右翼思想は外界[世間・社会]から孤立した[隔絶された状態]空間を求めるという(これは下記引用の―ドゥルーズ=ガタリの意味での―にあるが「smooth」な訳でも「striated」な訳でもない)。そしてこれは「the wealthy person is not self-made, in a vacuum」と全体主義の文脈で論じられていたように対照的な宇宙論なのである。 〜Deleuze and Guattari, of course, distinguishes between “smooth space” and “striated space”. Putting matters very crudely, a smooth space is a space of freedom like the steppes or the ocean, where there is not yet a grid dividing up space and where movement is possible in all directions. They argue (and I won’t get into this now) that it is a space populated by intensities and events. A striated space, by contrast, is highly structured and constraining. Here, for example, we should think about the game of chess. The striated nature of the game of chess lies not so much in the fact that the board is composed of squares, but rather because each piece has a fixed identity defining the movements of which it is capable (bishops can only move diagonally, rooks only horizontally and vertically, etc).Neither the concept of smooth space, nor the concept of striated space quite gets at the onto-spatial underpinnings of neoliberal thought. What we need is something like vacuum space.
What we need is something like vacuum space. Vacuum space is a conception of being without something like Heideggerian thrownness, where there are no obstacles facing us, where space is completely empty, and where everything is reduced down to the choices we make rather than the choices we face. It is the space underlying the intellectualist fallacy that Bourdieu so compellingly and trenchantly criticizes in Pascalian Meditations where all agents are treated as formally equivalent. For example, the economist is thinking in terms of vacuum space when he reduces agents to rational actors such that there are no circumstantial or relevant differences between men, women, gay, straight, believers, non-believers, different ethnic groups, people of different classes, etc. Here the agent is thought, for all intents and purposes, as being suspended in a vacuum. we are probably more defined not by the choices we make, but the choices we face.
右翼は「Neoliberal thought reduces everything down to choices we make」であるし、左翼は―後に述べられるように―「the problem with holism is that it undermines the possibility of agency.」である。つまり右翼の絶対的個人主権はホリスティックな影響を抑圧し、左翼はあらゆる問題をホリスティックなものとして個人の「possibility」を抑圧(undermines)してしまうのだ。だからこそ「choices we face」によって定義されるわたしたち、という直面するまでの全体主義性とそこから選択する個人主義性を接合するOOO politicsを、第三の次元として提唱する。そしてそこで「rat in a maze」の例を用いて「OOO politics」の空間を説明する
In the maze depicted to the rat, the rat doesn’t simply make choices, but faces choices as a result of how the walls and paths of the maze are constructed. Let’s suppose that the entrance to the maze is birth and the exit to the maze is death (our maze is not merely spatial, but is spatio-temporal). The rat can make choices, it can wander around in the maze, but the paths the rat can take are more or less predelineated in a way that constrains the choices that the rat can make. “Will I go left or right? Forward or backward? Will I stand still and wait?”
https://scrapbox.io/files/65a1e959d6e5f000242980fd.png
One of the major projects of social and political variants of OOO, I believe, is to map these negative feedback systems, these choices agents face, and the basins of attraction they generate. This entails a situated form of analysis that refuses our tendency towards thinking in terms of vacuum space. It requires the mapping of institutions, geographies, technologies, networks of communication and contact, etc., etc., etc. ~The point of an OOO politics is not simply to map negative feedback systems or regimes of attraction. No, diagrammatology or speculative cartography is only a first step.
こうして第一歩目としてのレジーム理解のために「cartography」を作る必要性を解く。「these negative feedback systems, these choices agents face, and the basins of attraction they generate」をマッピングし、「 situated form of analysis 」を行うこと「OOO politics」なのである。ブライアントが自身のOOOのverを「cybernetic-OOO」とするのはこの意味にあるのではないか。 ブライアントの転向
Here, then, I’m in a position to revise my position on fictions and symbolic entities. With Graham I’m able to agree that fictions and symbolic entities are not real entities, but rather are sensual objects. They are entities that only exist on the interior of a real object analogous to the manner in which Graham’s monster only exists in the interior of his mind. A fictional text such as Harry Potter cannot exist independently of the social assemblage (larger scale object) in which it occurs. A meme cannot exist as a substance in its own right. The value of money cannot exist as a substance or real object. All of these entities are sensual objects belonging to real objects– the social assemblage in which they exist. Nonetheless, through the mereological claims of OOO I am able to make a place for the objectivity and transcendence of these entities with respect to individual persons. These are sensual objects belonging to larger scale objects such as institutions and social assemblages, not individual persons. Because we are entangled with these larger scale objects, these sensual objects become constraints on our existence that we must navigate, just as we must walk around large boulders when taking a leisurely stroll in the forest.
つまりここで示しているのはフラットな存在論の立場―「In the past, I have argued that fictions are real entities.」―を修正し、「相対主義ではなく、むしろ最大限に徹底した実在論」というハーマン的立場への転向である。つまり虚構(fiction)や象徴的存在者(symbolic entities)は感覚的オブジェクトだと認めた上で、制度や社会的集合体などの大きなスケールに属する「客観性」と「超越性」を帯びた感覚的オブジェクトであることを主張するのである―この意味で個人に依存する従来の感覚的オブジェクトとは異なるのである。そしてそれこそが虚構の存在論的地位なのであり、それの最たる例がいわゆる下記のような貨幣と犯罪なのだ。犯罪の所以を個人の残滓にみるハーマンに対してGlennは「would have to rely on a definition of criminality external to the ‘object’」などとフーコー的な批判をする・ In the past, I have argued that fictions are real entities. My motive for this has had less to do with any particular fascination with fictions, but rather with peculiar properties of symbolic entities. Take the example of money. The value of money is, alas, not dependent on my mind. It has a value that transcends my will and intentionality, and which is therefore objective. I can’t make it have whatever value I wish it to have. Likewise with linguistic meaning and structure, as well as a host of social categories. ~ If I understand Glenn correctly, his point is that criminality is not in the so-called criminal. “Criminal” is not a quality of a substance (the person), but is rather a category within which the person finds himself situated as if a fish in a net.
ブライアントの「I need an ontological framework that is capable of theorizing the objectivity and transcendence of things like categories that nonetheless avoids treating them as real substances. Put differently, how can I theorize these sorts of beings within the framework of Graham’s fourfold?」といった言明はこの意味で理解しなければならない。つまり「客観性」と「超越性」をもった実在的オブジェクトではないものを、オブジェクト指向存在論に則って整理したことによってブライアントは自身の立場を修正するに至ったのである―補足になるがブライアントは『The Allure of Machinic Life』で「If you haven’t come across it already, go out and get yourself a copy of John Johnston’s Allure of Machinic Life: Cybernetics, Artificial Life, and the New AI immediately. This is quite simply the most exciting book I’ve read in recent memory and one I wish I’d come across when I was writing The Democracy of Objects (certain aspects of Johnston’s book are what I wish I’d written). 」と言っているように、この時点で『オブジェクトたちのデモクラシー』を書き終わっていることが想定されるゆえ、時系列上も、フラットな存在論からの転向は矛盾がない。 「cybernetic-OOO」という着想、そしてJohn Johnstonからのサイバネティクスの系譜が本論考である。そしてエントロピーとオブジェクトを節合することが本書の主題である。 https://scrapbox.io/files/6584e405c828320022fa0d59.jpeg